.
And by a prudent flight and cunning save A life which valour could not, from the grave. A better buckler I can soon regain, But who can get another life again?
Archilochus
Monday, June 16, 2025
What's My Part in this Band of Attention Seekers?
Moo!
btw - I HATE the Tuba and REFUSE to Play it! Now Trumpet...
...Trumpet will attract me a Strumpet!
Sunday, June 15, 2025
AdS/ CFT
Are Gravity and Time Emergent Properties that Don't Really Exist Yet Emerge through Entanglement from Thermal Properties on a flat 2D Quantum Space into 3D?
Welcome to Sphereland, home of the 'Flat' Earth Society!
From the Jowett Summary of Plato's "Laws"
But first I must pray the Gods to assist at the demonstration of their own existence—if ever we are to call upon them, now is the time. Let me hold fast to the rope, and enter into the depths: Shall I put the question to myself in this form?—Are all things at rest, and is nothing in motion? or are some things in motion, and some things at rest? 'The latter.' And do they move and rest, some in one place, some in more? 'Yes.' There may be (1) motion in the same place, as in revolution on an axis, which is imparted swiftly to the larger and slowly to the lesser circle; and there may be motion in different places, having sometimes (2) one centre of motion and sometimes (3) more. (4) When bodies in motion come against other bodies which are at rest, they are divided by them, and (5) when they are caught between other bodies coming from opposite directions they unite with them; and (6) they grow by union and (7) waste by dissolution while their constitution remains the same, but are (8) destroyed when their constitution fails. There is a growth from one dimension to two, and from a second to a third, which then becomes perceptible to sense; this process is called generation, and the opposite, destruction. We have now enumerated all possible motions with the exception of two. 'What are they?' Just the two with which our enquiry is concerned; for our enquiry relates to the soul. There is one kind of motion which is only able to move other things; there is another which can move itself as well, working in composition and decomposition, by increase and diminution, by generation and destruction. 'Granted.' (9) That which moves and is moved by another is the ninth kind of motion; (10) that which is self-moved and moves others is the tenth. And this tenth kind of motion is the mightiest, and is really the first, and is followed by that which was improperly called the ninth. 'How do you mean?' Must not that which is moved by others finally depend upon that which is moved by itself? Nothing can be affected by any transition prior to self-motion. Then the first and eldest principle of motion, whether in things at rest or not at rest, will be the principle of self-motion; and that which is moved by others and can move others will be the second. 'True.' Let me ask another question:
What is the name which is given to self-motion when manifested in any material substance? 'Life.' And soul too is life? 'Very good.' And are there not three kinds of knowledge—a knowledge (1) of the essence, (2) of the definition, (3) of the name? And sometimes the name leads us to ask the definition, sometimes the definition to ask the name. For example, number can be divided into equal parts, and when thus divided is termed even, and the definition of even and the word 'even' refer to the same thing. 'Very true.' And what is the definition of the thing which is named 'soul'? Must we not reply, 'The self-moved'? And have we not proved that the self-moved is the source of motion in other things? 'Yes.' And the motion which is not self-moved will be inferior to this? 'True.' And if so, we shall be right in saying that the soul is prior and superior to the body, and the body by nature subject and inferior to the soul? 'Quite right.' And we agreed that if the soul was prior to the body, the things of the soul were prior to the things of the body? 'Certainly.' And therefore desires, and manners, and thoughts, and true opinions, and recollections, are prior to the length and breadth and force of bodies. 'To be sure.' In the next place, we acknowledge that the soul is the cause of good and evil, just and unjust, if we suppose her to be the cause of all things? 'Certainly.' And the soul which orders all things must also order the heavens? 'Of course.' One soul or more? More; for less than two are inconceivable, one good, the other evil. 'Most true.' The soul directs all things by her movements, which we call will, consideration, attention, deliberation, opinion true and false, joy, sorrow, courage, fear, hatred, love, and similar affections. These are the primary movements, and they receive the secondary movements of bodies, and guide all things to increase and diminution, separation and union, and to all the qualities which accompany them—cold, hot, heavy, light, hard, soft, white, black, sweet, bitter; these and other such qualities the soul, herself a goddess, uses, when truly receiving the divine mind she leads all things rightly to their happiness; but under the impulse of folly she works out an opposite result. For the controller of heaven and earth and the circle of the world is either the wise and good soul, or the foolish and vicious soul, working in them. 'What do you mean?' If we say that the whole course and motion of heaven and earth is in accordance with the workings and reasonings of mind, clearly the best soul must have the care of the heaven, and guide it along that better way. 'True.' But if the heavens move wildly and disorderly, then they must be under the guidance of the evil soul. 'True again.' What is the nature of the movement of the soul? We must not suppose that we can see and know the soul with our bodily eyes, any more than we can fix them on the midday sun; it will be safer to look at an image only. 'How do you mean?' Let us find among the ten kinds of motion an image of the motion of the mind. You remember, as we said, that all things are divided into two classes; and some of them were moved and some at rest. 'Yes.' And of those which were moved, some were moved in the same place, others in more places than one. 'Just so.' The motion which was in one place was circular, like the motion of a spherical body; and such a motion in the same place, and in the same relations, is an excellent image of the motion of mind. 'Very true.' The motion of the other sort, which has no fixed place or manner or relation or order or proportion, is akin to folly and nonsense. 'Very true.' After what has been said, it is clear that, since the soul carries round all things, some soul which is either very good or the opposite carries round the circumference of heaven. But that soul can be no other than the best. Again, the soul carries round the sun, moon, and stars, and if the sun has a soul, then either the soul of the sun is within and moves the sun as the human soul moves the body; or, secondly, the sun is contained in some external air or fire, which the soul provides and through which she operates; or, thirdly, the course of the sun is guided by the soul acting in a wonderful manner without a body. 'Yes, in one of those ways the soul must guide all things.' And this soul of the sun, which is better than the sun, whether driving him in a chariot or employing any other agency, is by every man called a God? 'Yes, by every man who has any sense.' And of the seasons, stars, moon, and year, in like manner, it may be affirmed that the soul or souls from which they derive their excellence are divine; and without insisting on the manner of their working, no one can deny that all things are full of Gods. 'No one.' And now let us offer an alternative to him who denies that there are Gods. Either he must show that the soul is not the origin of all things, or he must live for the future in the belief that there are Gods.
Saturday, June 14, 2025
Friday, June 13, 2025
We're ALL in 2nd Order Observation Mode Now!
Always Performing for Others, yet Watching Ourselves in that Performance.
The Commodification of Land, Labout, Capital, and now, Personal Information (aka- The Self)
Thursday, June 12, 2025
Tuesday, June 10, 2025
Identity vs. Morality
The flaws in this video? Assuming "heredity and race" are the foundational units of "identity" and NOT the Civic Constitution: The Ordo Caritatis. Another, that morality extends beyond the self. The only "friendly" Morality based Ethic is as Kant categorically defined it, that of "Not imposing your will upon any others, treating them not as a means to an end, but as ends unto themselves.
And no, Identity isn't "better" than morality. Morality is "inward" facing, it's what I think of Me (and yes it may be based upon the ethics imposed by others like shame, guilt, pride, etc.) Identity, on the other hand, is more "outward facing" like a mask and often based in ethics imposed by others. Identity is a mask that I outwardly present and which defines me for "The Other" and what I want "The Other" to know or think about me and which lets him know what he can expect from me. It varies dependent upon the role in life's masquerade I am fulfilling (father, brother, worker, citizen, boss, representative). Today it is often on-line (24/7/365), both curated and and profilic.
What the videographer calls "Universal Morality" or "the Pseudo-Moral frame" in the video is really the "Ethics of Kitsch". It's he Secular Ethic of the Globalist/ Universalist. The "lover of all". The cosmopolitan humanist. The value he theologically places "above" that of his actual social/ civic constitution, that of his nation.
Technically, I'm Amish...
“We become what we behold. We shape our tools, and thereafter our tools shape us.”
Rule by Legal Processes...
...and centralization of Executive Information and Ensuring a Unitary Executive:
Deep State entities within the Executive Branch will no longer be able to hide their activities in information silos from their superiors. If the deep state is going to help Ukraine target Russian strategic bombers, the president will know what the USIC is up to. Ai will be watching them. The USIC will find themselves within the panopticon, and not stationed unobserved within its' central observation tower cloaked by National Security Ring of Gyges and invisible to the DNI. She will possess the "one ring to rule them all". will it corrupt her? Or empower her to actually become the "Director" of National Intelligence?
So, either repeal the Patriot Act and stop spying on Americans ENTIRELY or let the DNI do her job, and the President his.
For Popper's Open Society
Selected excerpts and notes from the video above:
"What we need and what we want... is to moralize politics, not to politicize morals."- PopperMoralize Politics: Apply ethical standards to political actionPopper did not deny the existence of objective moral truths, what he denied was the State's right to impose them as fixed certainties.
Politicize Morals: Enshrine one moral code as unchangeable law
"Identity has increasingly filled the void left by the absence of shared cultural and moral frameworks. Religion, nationality, and even biological sex have become battlegrounds where individuals seek personal meaning. This cultural transformation began at Universities, but as Andrew Sullivan argues in his essay "We all live on Campus now," it quickly spread into journalism, corporations , and government."
The post-modernists moral relativism was replaced by a new kind of moral certainty rooted in identity and lived experience rather than universal principles. Once truth was recast as power, traditional norms lost legitimacy, and so did the very idea of open disagreement. University politics on microaggressions and trigger warnings reflect a new moral framework in which harm is measured subjectively and debate can itself be construed as aggression. Many students now interpret words as violence, and view disagreement as a for of disrespect or invalidation.
The failure to defend the cultural and civic infrastructure that once gave openness coherence, and provided moral depth. Liberal societies are not adrift because they honored openness too much, but because they ceased to defend the cultural and civic infrastructure that once gave that openness coherence and provided moral depth.
Bureaucratic centralization further weakened community self-government by displacing local initiative. As Uval Levven observes in "The Fractured Republic", a nationalized political culture has increasingly crowded out the middle layers of society, the local associations that once formed the bedrock of civil life. In the UK, local authorities now raise only a fraction of the revenue they spend, leaving them heavily dependent on central government transfers, and limiting their scope for local innovation or accountability. A 2022 report by Center for Cities concluded that Britain has become one of the most fiscally centralized countries in the developed world. As Phillip Blond has argued in "Red Tory", "The state and the market have conspired to hollow out civil society, leaving individuals atomized and communities fragmented."
The decline in civic education. Civic education provides a shared vocabulary about the common good without requiring a shared theology or ethnicity. Civic enfranchisement depends on a shared base of knowledge. Without it, democratic deliberation breaks down.
The erosion has also been cultural.
The model d' Toqueville observed in 19th century America still works. The evidence is particularly striking in Denmark. Denmark consistently ranks among the world's most cohesive and high trust democracies. Its' cohesion stems from strong civic networks supported by public institutions that are transparent, responsive, and widely trusted.
The civic religion must be taught. Over time citizens can come to emotionally identify with a new second patriotism founded upon the Constitution. However, this patriotism must be taught. When schools fail to transmit a common base of knowledge, it would be hard to invent a more effective recipe for cultural fragmentation. Nations need stories they can tell about themselves that are forward-looking, inclusive, and cohesive. A society paralyzed by shame will not survive, nor will one built on nostalgia.
Constitutional patriotism, then, can live in story, education, ritual, and shared public life. In this way, liberal democracies can foster cohesion without succumbing to the exclusionary certainties of the strong gods.
Liberal societies should also recover the civic power of local communities. Excessive centralization has weakened the middle layers of society, displacing voluntary institutions and disempowering citizens. One remedy is subsidiarity, shifting decision making closer to those affected by it. Switzerland exemplifies this with a federal system that gives substantial autonomy to Cantons and Communes and engages citizens directly through referenda. These decentralized models offer a way to restore civic belonging without restoring top-down cultural unity.
Liberal societies also need clear moral and civic boundaries. Mutual tolerance should not be a suicide pact. Immigration can enrich liberal societies- but only if newcomers accept core liberal principles. Inclusion requires clarity. The price for admission to a liberal democracy should be respect for the rules that make peaceful coexistence possible. That includes rejective efforts from any quarter to impose religious orthodoxy, racial essentialism, or ideological loyalty tests.
The current turn towards strong gods reflects a fear that Open Societies can no longer provide meaning. That fear is misplaced. Liberal societies need not imitate sacred authority to inspire belonging, but they must stop outsourcing meaning to the very sources that threaten them. The Open Society will only endure if it is made into something people can believe in again - because it delivers not just rights but prosperity; not just institutions, but ideals worth committing to. The real test is not whether liberalism should resurrect the religious or nationalist certainties of the past, but whether it can rebuild the civic and cultural foundations that allow meaning and freedom to flourish together.
In other words, an Open Society should be based upon economically independent and small, local but fiscally-independent, anti-fragile communities with strongly enforced boundaries operating within a framework mediated by a strong National Constitutionally based civic religion.
Salvador Dali, "The Old Age of William Tell"
Monday, June 9, 2025
Neo-Liberalism: Last Men Smothering the World with Totalitarian and Oppressive Love?
Matthew McManus,"Nietzsche's Critique of Liberalism"
Liberal institutions straightway cease from being liberal, the moment they are soundly established: once this is attained no more grievous and more thorough enemies of freedom exist than liberal institutions! One knows, of course, what they bring about: they undermine the Will to Power, they are the levelling of mountain and valley exalted to a morality, they make people small, cowardly and pleasure-loving,—by means of them the gregarious animal invariably triumphs. Liberalism, or, in plain English, the transformation of mankind into cattle… Freedom is the will to be responsible for ourselves. It is to preserve the distance which separates us from other men. To grow more indifferent to hardship, to severity, to privation, and even to life itself. To be ready to sacrifice men for one’s cause, one’s self included. Freedom denotes that the virile instincts which rejoice in war and in victory, prevail over other instincts; for instance, over the instincts of “happiness.” The man who has won his freedom, and how much more so, therefore, the spirit that has won its freedom, tramples ruthlessly upon that contemptible kind of comfort which tea—grocers, Christians, cows, women, Englishmen and other democrats worship in their dreams. The free man is a warrior.- Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols
Many are the angry counter-cultural intellectuals who declare themselves a “destiny” but few are those who are much more than a 15-minute idiosyncrasy. Nietzsche is one of those very few who truly achieved the epochal significance he—half joking, half deadly serious—projected for himself in Ecce Homo. That Nietzsche slipped into madness and the not-so-tender care of his Nazi-sympathizing and anti-Semitic sister just as his influence was about to take off is one of the great tragedies in philosophy. One can only guess at the number of vulgar interpretations of his work which might have prevented.
Nietzsche’s reputation has gone through a remarkable roller coaster since he passed away in 1900. Hard-nosed analytical philosophers like Bertrand Russell took a dim view of Nietzsche’s contributions, finding them wildly declaratory and bombastic. In his History of Western Philosophy Russell summarized Nietzsche’s outlook with a line from King Lear: “I will do such things—What they are yet I know not——but they shall be The terror of the earth.” Nevertheless his reputation amongst the broader intelligentsia, from James Joyce to W. B. Yeats, grew rapidly. In the leadup and aftermath of the Second World War, the view of Nietzsche again soured as many took the Nazis at their word that he was a predecessor to their views. In his The Destruction of Reason the great Western Marxist Gyorgy Lukas centered Nietzsche as the great “irrationalist” of the 19th century who paved the way for Nazi hostility towards the “masses” and veneration of a new and violent aristocracy.
But the power of Nietzsche’s thinking couldn’t be denied, nor could his profound influence on diverse postwar figures like Jean Paul Sartre, Leo Strauss, Ayn Rand and countless others. This led to a reevaluation of Nietzsche’s value, spearheaded above all by the great Walter Kaufmann’s lucid and evocative translations of Nietzsche’s work which became standard across the Anglo world. In his seminal Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Anti-Christ, Kaufmann read Nietzsche as precursor to then-ubiquitous existential individualism. Alienated, counter-cultural, and deep of course. But effectively apolitical, and certainly nothing as crude and vulgar as the Nazi portrait of Nietzsche as a barbarous proto-Fascist. At most he was a bohemian individualist; a kind of spiritual artist as beyond politics as he was good and evil.
The screw turned again in the 1960s as Nietzsche was discovered by a generation of New Left and post-structuralist thinkers on both sides of the Atlantic. They embraced Nietzsche’s perspectivism, method of historical genealogy, and fascination with power in a number of highly creative ways. Gilles Deleuze and Michel Foucault both developed a popular “post-modern” view of Nietzsche as a philosopher who resisted normalization and celebrated a healthy distinctiveness against the pressures of discipline or control. Foucault even declared that he was “simply a Nietzschean” who developed Nietzsche’s views on morality and power to demonstrate that values asserted as universal and rational in fact rested on forces of disciplinary oppression.
On the other side of the Atlantic, the great left-liberal Richard Rorty internalized the perspectivist Nietzsche of “On Truth and Lies in a Non-Moral Sense” where the latter described truth as a “moving army of metaphors, metonymies, and anthropomorphisms: in short, a sum of human relations which have been poetically and rhetorically intensified, transferred, and embellished, and which, after long usage, seem to a people to be fixed, canonical, and binding.” Rorty hoped that the extension of this Nietzschean outlook would help gentle the fanaticism and fundamentalism of political conflict, especially that coming from the political right. As he put it in Philosophy and Social Hope Philosophy and Social Hope “rightist thinkers don’t think that it is enough just to prefer democratic societies. One also has to believe that they are Objectively Good, that the institutions of such societies are grounded in Rational First Principles…My own philosophical views—view I share with Nietzsche and Dewey—forbid me to say this kind of thing.”
It was this Nietzsche that I came of age reading and this Nietzsche that many conservatives attacked for his influence on the counter-cultural left. And to be clear, I think there is still considerable value in liberal and left readings of Nietzschean themes which repurpose his work for progressive ends. Nietzsche may have despised readers who acted like “plundering troops” who take away a few things, while distorting the “whole.” But I see no reason to adopt a tone of pious reverence towards an author who self-identified as the Anti-Christ and who himself liberally drew ideas from a wide array of disciplines and themes. However, while it may be permissible to appropriate Nietzsche for liberals and progressives we must be very clear that we are using weapons he intended be directed against us. This is because Nietzsche’s thought, regarded as a “whole” constitutes one of the most profound and sweeping rejections of egalitarian modernity ever seen.
Nietzsche and the contemporary radical right
In a cycle of eternal recurrence which might have amused him, we are now seeing another new interpretation of Nietzsche appear. A new interpretation which is in fact an old one, but filtered through the concerns of our cultural moment. This is Nietzsche the aristocratic radical and fanatical opponent of liberalism, socialism, and democracy. His presence has grown so ubiquitous that commentators are now regularly talking about the “Nietzschean” right and its influence on American politics. It can be juxtaposed against the more religious “post-liberal” right of figures like Patrick Deneen, or the “national conservatism” of Yoram Hazony as the third leg of the new three legged stool of the American right. In theory the overt religiosity and communitarian ethos shared by post-liberalism and national conservatism should inhibit a tight embrace of Nietzschean tropes. In practice things become more complicated.
In an amusing twist, the nominally Christian magazine First Things has published figures who offer discounted Nietzschean bombast like Lom3Z. In his essay, Lom3Z condemns the “Longhouse,” which encompasses “technocratic governance” but also “wokeness”and all that is “progressive” “liberal” and “secular.” This needs to be confronted since it “distrusts overt ambition. It censures the drive to assert oneself on the world, to strike out for conquest and expansion. Male competition and the hierarchies that drive it are unwelcome. Even constructive expressions of these instincts are deemed toxic, patriarchal, or even racist.” This shows the extent to which the Nietzschean right has become a major cultural player.
The modern Nietzschean right was willed into being by proponents like Richard Spencer and the alt-right, who leaned heavily on the thinking of the “Conservative Revolution” in Weimar Germany. Nietzschean ideas have since gained traction through popularizations like Bronze Age Mindset, which includes truly endless whining about the influence of soft progressive “bugmen” and calls for a new aristocracy of coconut oil glazed musclemen. These ideas have gained considerable traction with young conservative radicals in search of a more muscular rejection of liberal “effeminacy” and its replacement with a butch ethos of unconstrained power. That many of the proponents of these views are terminally online nebbish intellectuals who’d struggle to cosplay as “super-duper” Conan the Barbarians is a major paradox of praxis the Nietzschean right has yet to resolve.
The American Nietzschean right once more combines Nietzsche with various forms of nationalism and crude racist biologism. This is the temptation generations of interpreters tried to ward off because of its transparent Nazi associations; usually by pointing to Nietzsche’s condemnations of anti-Semitism and his cosmopolitan insistence on being a “good European” in Beyond Good and Evil. But the allure of a more populist Nietzsche remains an enduring idol, and its not hard to see why. One of the major tropes of right-wing populism has been the struggle to extend notions of aristocracy and status downwards to build support for hierarchical policies amongst the lower orders who may feel invested in upending them. Not coincidentally Southern antebellum racists were particularly gifted at this, with James DeBow insisting that “the color of the white man is now, in the south, a title of nobility” and observing that poor whites in the North are “at the bottom of the social ladder, whilst [their] brother here has ascended several steps and can look down upon those who are beneath him, at an infinite remove.”
Nietzsche offers an aristocratic grammar and outlook that can be extended to the national level through proclamations that one belongs to a great people who have been humiliated and shamed by decadent and corrupting egalitarian enemies. Once these enemies are overcome by a rarefied elite of super-duper men, this Eminem blonde people can once more fulfill its grand destiny through palingenetic renewal. While technically at cross purposes with Nietzsche’s exclusion of all demotic politics, this offers a useful way to drum up popular support for the far right in the same way figures like DeBow hoped to induce poor whites to fight and eventually die for the slave system that ultimately benefited the masters above all else. Bronze Age Pervert even concedes the need for these kinds of Nietzschean compromises with Machiavelli. In Bronze Age Mindset, when he isn’t congratulating himself for coming up with coining some neologism as an insult, Pervy the Populist encourages his followers to “make alliance with people who otherwise wouldn’t be your friends. I believe that democracy is the final cause of all the political problems I describe here, but in the short run democracy—the will of the people—is on our side because the democracies have been hijacked by a stupid and corrupt elite.
The nations face extinction and an era of permanent civil war because this elite wants to pillage and pillage: and wants to flood them with the shit of the world. This is the immediate threat, and on this you can be allied with people who otherwise may not shoot for the same star you do. If Ann Coulter or Pat Buchanan were in charge, you would get 99% of what you want. Therefore use them as models to solve the problems that face you, and don’t scare the peoples with crazy talk if you want to move things politically. Let the normies have their normal lives, and paint our enemies as the crazies…which they are…and as the corrupt vermin they are. If you haven’t compromised yourself go into political life maybe, and use Trump as a model for success.”
Nietzsche, the aristocratic radical
One of the major condemnations of the Nietzschean right is that they’ve failed to read the master correctly. “Drunk on bad readings” of Nietzsche as Vox’s Sean Illing put it. And in many cases that is true, as any careful reading of Nietzsche would encourage people with taste as tediously crass as the far right to refrain from depleting the culture through their “contributions.”
But this approach only goes so far. Focusing on the far right’s misreadings risks insulating Nietzsche from critique out of a desire to make him safe for liberals and the left. In his magisterial Nietzsche, The Aristocratic Rebel Domenico Losurdo refers to this as the “hermeneutics of innocence” Its ironic that a thinker as obsessed with “hard” thoughts as Nietzsche— who read virtually every major figure in philosophy with suspicion—would be the beneficiary of such a velvet touch.
For the remainder of this essay I’ll discuss what I consider Nietzsche’s own political views, following Malcolm Bull’s correct observation in Anti-Nietzsche that “equality has had no fiercer critic than Nietzsche, whose ‘fundamental insight with respect to the genealogy of morals’ is that social inequality is the source of our value concepts, and the necessary condition of value itself. His rejection of equality is unequivocal.” So entranced with Nietzsche was this notion that he even pre-emptively rejected the popular Kaufmannesque take on his philosophy as individualist, declaring in The Will to Power that his “…philosophy aims at an ordering of rank: not at an individualistic morality. The ideas of the herd should rule in the herd – but not reach out beyond it.” That is when he wasn’t declaring that the “great majority of men have no right to life, and serve only to disconcert the elect among our race; I do not yet grant the unfit that right. There are even unfit people.”
Nietzsche’s political thinking went through a number of evolutions which have kept scholars busy for years. His work as a whole is usually divided into an early period between 1871-1876 when Nietzsche published The Birth of Tragedy and other Wagner inflected works on culture and the Greeks. The most famous idea to arise during this time was Nietzsche’s famous contrast between Apollonian and Dionysian approaches to reality, with Nietzsche inveighing against the Enlightenment optimism of the former. Nietzsche also resists liberalism’s individualism and attempt to orient life around economic production and consumption, even finding transient charms in Prussian militarism and its war against French revolutionary demagoguery.
In An Introduction to Nietzsche as Political Thinker, Keith-Answell Pearson argues that in Nietzsche’s mid period between 1878-1882, he transitioned to being a kind of ultra-elitist champion of “the aims of the Enlightenment, and promoting the cause of a rationalist, critical theory.” Both Lukacs and Losurdo argue Nietzsche embraced a kind of aristocratic liberalism during the era—embracing the principles of free thought and expression amongst the elite, and even occasionally seeing a bright side of marginal democratization. But this was not to last, and Nietzsche came to feel nothing but contempt for both decadent liberals and soft conservatives who tried to rule the masses by placating their most venal desires. Instead, the confrontation with nihilism would require a new kind of politics which was violent, stimulating, and stimulated the strength of those worthy of being strong.
By the time of The Gay Science Nietzsche is already suggesting he’s onto something original and difficult to label, insisting that he wishes to ‘conserve’ nothing, neither do we want to return to any past periods, we are not by any means ‘liberal’; we do not work for ‘progress’; we do not need to plug up our ears against the sirens who in the marketplace sing of the future: their song about ‘equal rights,’ ‘a free society,’ ‘no more masters and no more servants’ has no allure for us. We simply do not consider it desirable that a realm of justice and concord should be established on earth…we are delighted with all who love, as we do, danger, war, and adventure, who refuse to compromise, to be captured, reconciled, and castrated; we count ourselves among conquerors; we think about the necessity for new orders, also for a new slavery—for every strengthening and enhancement of the human type also involves a new kind of enslavement.”
It is in the works of Nietzsche’s maturity (1882—1889) that he developed the most refined view of his politics and his most creative set of ideas. This was undeniably a time of great energy and inspiration for Nietzsche, with Thus Spoke Zarathustra appearing in 1883 and the publication of no less than seven major works between 1886—1888 alone. Nietzsche often promised the publication of a grand systematic work, The Will to Power, that would bring all his major ideas together into a whole, but it never came to be before he descended into madness (the work published under that name was written by Nietzsche, but was a collection of statements largely organized by his sister).
Nevertheless there is a clear political philosophy in the mature Nietzsche which was new and deserves attention. Probably the most programmatic statement in Nietzsche’s oeuvre appears in the mature work Beyond Good and Evil, where he lays out his utopian vision for the ideal society.Every elevation of the type ‘man,’ has hitherto been the work of an aristocratic society—and so it will always be: a society which believes in a long scale of orders of rank and differences of worth between man and man and needs slavery in some sense or other. Without the pathos of distance such as develops from the incarnate differences of classes, from the ruling caste’s constant looking out and looking down on subjects and instruments and from its equally constant exercise of obedience and command, its holding down and holding at a distance, that other, more mysterious pathos could not have developed either…in short precisely the elevation of the type ‘man’, the continual ‘self-overcoming of man,’ to take a moral formula in a supra-moral sense.As is often the case, the language purrs with suggestive connotation even where it is not subtle but brutal. In correspondence with Nietzsche, the Danish critic Georg Brandes described his thinking as a kind of “aristocratic radicalism,” and the former approved the view. This leads to the question of why this required a rejection of liberalism, socialism, and democracy, and what aristocratic radicalism would entail.
The pathos of distanceThe poison of the doctrine ‘equal rights for all’—this has been more thoroughly sowed by Christianity than by anything else, from the most secret recesses of base instincts, Christianity has waged a war to the death against every feeling of reverence and distance between man and man, against, that is, the precondition of every elevation, every increase in culture—it has forged out of the ressentiment of the masses its chief weapon against us.- Friedrich Nietzsche, The Anti-Christ
Nietzsche is the greatest right wing thinker of all time because he had the audacity to go further and more boldly where other defenders of aristocracy and hierarchy still fear to tread. His originality comes from the sweep and depth of his critique of egalitarian modernity, which inverts the progressive liberal and socialist trajectory to characterize history as a long fall into nihilism.
There’s no doing full justice to the sweep of Nietzsche’s arguments in an article, let alone a full contrast with other thinkers (though I attempt this at book length in The Political Right and Equality). To put it simply, esteemed right wing thinkers from Robert Filmer through Joseph de Maistre shared many of Nietzsche’s reservations about the Enlightenment claim that all individuals possess a capacity for reason (even if this proposition was reserved at first for straight, male, white, propertied individuals), and were therefore capable of deliberating on and criticizing political authority. This in turn led to calls for political equality and participation, opening the door to a world of demanding citizens rather than complacent subjects.
The right’s most sparkling intellects reacted with a mixture of alarm and disdain. The connective tissue between them is a sense that the low “herd” might well triumph, bringing about a transformative change in society. But to avoid glamorizing this excessively, this transformative change was invariably deflated by the right. A world run by the herd would be one filled with endless talk and deliberation about banalities, lacking energy and drama. De Maistre characterized Enlightenment philosophy as a fundamentally “destructive” force since it opened authority to endless contestation, rather than treating it as a creed. From the beginning Burke and De Maistre contrasted what they saw as the staid values of the herd with the sublime “pleasing illusions” and emotions stirred by submission to resplendent aristocratic power. For them, the ascent of the herd guaranteed a world devoid of color and meaning, lacking the splendor and awe that could only come from projecting sublimity onto power to transform it into authority.
De Maistre even evoked proto-Nietzschean language about how it is “always an oracle, which founds cities; it is always an oracle, which announces the Divine protection, and successes of the heroic founder. Kings, especially, the chiefs of rising empires, are constantly designated, and, as it were, marked, by Heaven, in some extraordinary manner.” Or elsewhere claiming that “lawgivers, strictly speaking, are extraordinary men, belonging perhaps only to the ancient world and to the youth of nations. Providence has decreed the more rapid formation of a political constitution, there appears a man clothed with an indefinable power; he speaks, and he makes himself to be obeyed.” De Maistre also shared with Nietzsche a keen admiration for the animating excitement of violence, and how it imbued meaning to life through bringing individuals out of their mundane concerns with self-gratification and elevating their feelings to an existential pitch.
But conventional conservatives and reactionaries often ended their critiques of liberalism, socialism, and democracy at the Reformation. As Don Herzog points out in his seminal Poisoning the Minds of the Lower Orders, the early right had a deep nostalgia for a flavor of Christianity (often assisted by Aristotelianism) that emphasized the hierarchical structure of society. Natural human hierarchies on earth were conceived as coextensive, and participating in, more sublime hierarchies set by God. An eminent example is the popular image of a “Great Chain of Being” running from God, through his angels, to kings and downwards. For many of them, it was the decline of religious dogmatism which led to the Age of Reason and then the endless Age of Revolution. The goal was to deny the universality or even use of reason next to “dogma” or “faith” or even just the use-value of tradition, and go back to the more meaning-saturated cosmos of the Medieval era.
Nietzsche’s brilliance came from entirely rejecting this line of argument after his middle period, often lampooning this form of nostalgic conservatism as comically ineffective. In a short section of Twilight of the Idols he “whispered to conservatives” that such “a reversion, a return in any sense or degree is simply not possible. We physiologists know that. Yet all priests and moralists have believed the opposite—they wanted to take mankind back, to screw it back, to a former measure of virtue. Morality was always a bed of Procrustes. Even the politicians have aped the preachers of virtue at this point: today too there are still parties whose dream it is that all things might walk backwards like crabs.” Part of his revulsion was disturbingly anticipatory, as Nietzsche chastised conservative elites the same the far right today chastises RINOS: as lacking nerve and a willingness to truly use violence and domination to put the people back in their place.
In the same book Nietzsche sneers at conservative elites who think it is sensible to educate the people, even marginally, and iterates his familiar call for the reintroduction of slavery in German society. Domenico Losurdo stresses how these passages are directed against very conservative German imperial government, which Nietzsche chastizes for being too benevolent towards the workers movement. This ranged from providing various forms of education to introducing, mostly nominal and intentionally ineffective, ways for the masses to participate in politics. Nietzsche lamented the effect these concessions had on the lower orders in imperial Germany, moaning that they will only foster a sense of equality on the part of workers and make it impossible to produce “a modest and self-sufficient kind of human being, a type of Chinaman…” He goes on to groan that the “worker has been made liable for military service, he has been allowed to form unions and to vote: no wonder the worker already feels his existence to be a state of distress (expressed in moral terms as a state of injustice). But what does one want?—to ask it again. If one ills and end, one must also will the means to it: if one wants slaves, one is a fool if one educates them to be masters.”
But the deeper basis for Nietzsche’s rejection of conservatism lies in its failure to recognize the real roots of the problem. That is that liberalism, socialism, and democracy aren’t breaks from the Christian tradition of yore. They are its secular continuation. People like Jordan Peterson can complain about declining Judeo-Christian values as much as they want: from Nietzsche’s standpoint it is the post-modern neo-Marxists (or meta-Marxists, or whatever Marxists they are this week) who are the real heirs to the Christian axiom that the wretched of the earth will have their day. This is also where Nietzsche’s intellectual and political radicalness lie, since he recognizes that any overturning of these decadent modern ideologies will also require the emphatic rejection of Christianity.
Nietzsche’s most sustained arguments for this position are made in The Genealogy of Morals and The Anti-Christ. In short, pre-Christian and especially Greek societies were characterized by an aristocratic and healthy “master morality” that divided the world into good and bad. Goodness was what beatified and strengthened the most rarefied persons and was associated with the proud nobility, and badness was aligned with slavish ugliness of the masses. Unable or unwilling to seek revenge against their masters in the physical world, the slave class directed their feelings of resentiment inwards until they became creative. The consequence was the development of a new morality which declared the values of the masters to in fact be not just bad but “evil” while the proto-egalitarian and populist values of the slave were “good.” This was for Nietzsche the basis of the Christian morality, which in turn aligned itself with Platonic emphases on the value of “truth” to further divinize their feelings of resentiment by presenting them as universal moral facts. But eventually this “will to truth” central to Christianity came to compromise the faith since Christianity “…as a dogma was destroyed by its own morality, in the same way Christianity as morality must now perish to: we stand on the threshold of this event. After Christian truthfulness has drawn one inference after another, it must end by drawing its most striking inference, its inference against itself; this will happen, however, when it poses the question ‘what is the meaning of all will to truth.”
This “inference against itself” brought about Christianity’s own will to truth brought about an end to Christian metaphysics. But not, according to Nietzsche, Christian morality. Instead of abandoning the resentiment—driven Christian belief in reason and the universal equality of all human beings, the most creative modern thinkers such as Kant found ways to secularize them. Instead of reason being the handmaiden of faith in a better future in the afterlife, the scientific method became a tool to project an endlessly improving future in the profane world. Instead of moral rules being ordained by God, they came from “pure practical reason” or the doctrine of “utility” or the “doctrine” of “equal rights for all.” These secularized philosophical ideas laid the intellectual foundations for liberalism, socialism and democracy and were so successful their genealogical origins in Christianity became swallowed up and even repudiated.
Given this it should come as no surprise that many, but by no means all, on the Christian and nationalist right are keen to reject Nietzsche. And not just because his work critiques their worldview. As mentioned, taking Nietzsche’s thinking seriously would lead to the conclusion that it’s actually the Biden—Sanders—Cortez types who are doing the Lord’s work, while their hoary defenses of traditional privilege and the law are a kind of insincere halfway point between true Christianity and antiquity. Nietzsche had nothing but contempt for all of this, insisting in The Anti-Christ that above all he hated the “rabble of Socialists, the apostles to the Chandala, who undermine the workingman’s instincts, his pleasure, his feeling of contentment with his petty existence—who make him envious and teach him revenge…. Wrong never lies in unequal rights; it lies in the assertion of “equal” rights…. What is bad? But I have already answered: all that proceeds from weakness, from envy, from revenge.— The anarchist and the Christian have the same ancestry.” All these secular doctrines, from liberalism to socialism undermined the rabble’s instincts for submission and narrowed the “pathos of distance” between great and herd so necessary for the elevation of culture and resisting nihilism.
Resisting Nietzschean politics
Nietzschean aristocratic radicalism is a genuine threat to liberalism and all forms of progressivism because it offers those convinced of their own superiority a powerful and deep philosophy for them to dilute into cheap justifications for their own privilege. Nevertheless there are important ways that liberals can respond.
One of the first and most important is to turn the argument about Nietzschean resentiment on its head and point out the serious gap in his analysis. That is how the “masters” in any given society are very capable of their own forms of resentiment driven politics, down to even calling Trump the “only middle finger available” to stick it to liberalism. The allure of status and rank is in no small part its exclusionary qualities—the fact that one can enjoy status and rank while others can’t. Many forms of right wing politics are motivated by resentimment that that status and rank are being extended to others, even where that has no material impact on ones self. This contributes a lot to what Greg Sargent has rightly called the “MAGA Persecution Complex.” Many of the nativist forms of politics which lean on Nietzschean rhetoric are predicated on the idea that “our country” is being taken away or polluted by the presence of the unworthy, who dilute the esteem with which we can hold ourselves. This has deep roots in the political right in America, as when George Wallace threatened to close schools for all if they were desegregated. One can also see it in much of the vitriol directed at student debt forgiveness. While some of the conversation has centered on immediate economic burdens, much of the right’s rhetoric has taken the form of “if I didn’t get it, neither should they.” The MAGA persecution complex is difficult to understand without grasping this basis in resentiment.
But in the long run the more important task for liberals is to confront Nietzsche more directly and insist that equality and freedom for all are the long term answers to the threat of nihilism. Here we have a great deal to do. Liberal states are currently riven by deep inequalities which expose the stark contrast between high ideals and brutal realities. Neoliberal “possessive individualism” has contributed to a corrosive ethic where the poor are made to internalize a sense of blame for their own marginalization, and the rich come to think that they owe nothing to the people who do most of the working, sweating and dying in this country. This is an unsustainable situation and creates fertile ground for the siren’s call of those who insist the powerful are powerful because they truly are better. Or, in a more populist and resentful vein, that one belongs to a dispossessed elite whose coronation will come as soon as the decadent egalitarian bugmen living high in their cathedral are exterminated. For liberalism to become meaningful to all liberal states must show equal respect and concern to all. How to achieve that is the “heaviest burden” for those of us who believe in liberty, equality, and solidarity.
The Open Society: Where Transgression Becomes Conformity and Conformity, Transgressive
Why Politics became "Moralistic Anti-Politics" Rather than Reasonable and Rational:
R.R. Reno, "The Love Society and Its' Enemies"
The Philosophy of Neo-Liberalism
America's Establishment Uni-Party: Where Cultural Left and Economic Right "Openness" Join Hands and
Karl Popper and Friedrich Hayek Embrace
What Happened to Meden Agan (None/ Nothing too Much)?
Slavoj Žižek's work, particularly in The Sublime Object of Ideology, challenges the notion of an "end of ideology" (Strong Gods) championed by thinkers like Francis Fukuyama. He argues that ideology, far from disappearing, is deeply ingrained in contemporary society, operating through "doubling strategies" that simultaneously reveal and conceal its workings.
Sunday, June 8, 2025
Surplus Jouissance: Heliotropes of ἐπιθυμία
On James Joyce's "Finnegans Wake"
Polylogue vs. Dialogue
Heliotrope - The noun is borrowed from French héliotrope, from Latin hēliotropium (“plant which turns to face the sun; bloodstone”), from Ancient Greek ἡλῐοτρόπῐον (hēlĭotrópĭon, “European heliotrope (Heliotropium europaeum); bloodstone; solar clock, sundial”), from ἥλῐος (hḗlĭos, “the sun”) (ultimately from Proto-Indo-European *sóh₂wl̥ (“the sun”)) + τρόπος (trópos, “a turn”) (from τρέπω (trépō, “to rotate; to turn”) (from Proto-Indo-European *trep- (“to turn”)) + -ος (-os, suffix forming nouns from verbs)) + -ῐον (-ĭon, diminutive suffix forming nouns).[1]
ἐπιθυμία (epithumia):
The noun form, meaning "desire" or "longing". It can be used in both positive and negative contexts, encompassing both legitimate desires (like a longing for spiritual growth) and sinful desires (like coveting).
If we were flowers
We would worship the sun
So why not now?
This high is shining brightly
Brighter than before
Armeria Maritima "Bloodstone" (Sea Thrift)
Saturday, June 7, 2025
The Mystery of Biochemical Chirality
...and homochirality in Living forms
From Google AI:Assembly Theory incorporates the concept of chirality, particularly in the context of how complexity arises through the assembly of molecules and structures.1. Chirality and Assembly Theory's Focus:
- Chirality as a factor in complexity: Assembly theory focuses on measuring the complexity of objects, including molecules, by quantifying the minimum number of steps required to construct them from basic building blocks. Chirality, or "handedness", is a fundamental aspect of many molecules and structures, especially biological ones like proteins and DNA, and plays a vital role in their specific interactions and functions.
- Chirality and self-assembly: Chiral molecules can self-assemble into higher-order structures with specific chiral characteristics. The assembly process can be governed by the chirality of the building blocks themselves or through the induction of chirality in achiral molecules by external factors.
- Assembly theory quantifies selection: Assembly theory provides a framework for understanding how selection, whether in biological evolution or in other complex systems, leads to the emergence of complex objects like those with specific chirality. The theory suggests that the presence of multiple copies of objects with high assembly indices (meaning they require many steps to build) is evidence of selection at play.
2. How Chirality is Handled in Practice:
- Chiral building blocks: Assembly theory can account for the chirality of building blocks in determining the assembly pathways and ultimately the complexity of the resulting structure. For example, the self-assembly of chiral molecules into helical structures.
- Chiral induction: The theory can also encompass the influence of external factors or other molecules on inducing chirality in self-assembling systems, even if the primary building blocks are achiral.
3. Example from Research:
- Self-regulating chiral assemblies: Research on stimuli-responsive self-regulating assemblies of chiral and magnetically orientable nanorods demonstrates how chirality is incorporated within assembly theory. In this example, the effective chirality of the system can be modulated by a magnetic field, influencing the self-regulation mechanism that determines the size and shape of the assembled structures.
In summary, Assembly Theory addresses chirality by incorporating it as a structural property that contributes to the complexity of the assembled objects. The theory's framework, which focuses on assembly pathways and the role of selection, can be used to analyze and understand how chiral structures emerge and evolve.
Magnetic Fields for limb regeneration? The bio-electric field that influences structure formation?
More from Google AI:
Chirality can be induced in achiral structures through various mechanisms, including interactions with chiral environments, external stimuli, and self-assembly processes. These methods break the mirror symmetry of the achiral structure, leading to a preferred conformation or handedness that can be detected using chiroptical spectroscopy.Methods for Inducing Chirality in Achiral Structures:
Chiral Interactions:Interaction with a chiral environment, like a chiral host molecule or a chiral surface, can constrain the conformational freedom of an achiral guest molecule, leading to a preferred conformation and induced chirality. External Stimuli:Applying external stimuli like magnetic fields, pressure-driven flow, or confinement can induce chirality in achiral systems. For example, a pressure-driven flow in a microfluidic cell can create chiral structures in nematic liquid crystals. Self-Assembly:Achiral molecules can be organized into chiral supramolecular structures through self-assembly processes, such as those driven by solvophobic effects. Metal-Organic Frameworks (MOFs):Achiral precursors can be assembled into chiral MOFs by introducing external stimuli like pyridine or by using a kinetic-controlled assembly process. Chiral Ligand Interactions:Achiral and chiral ligands can be used synergistically to assemble inorganics into chiral superstructures by modulating the chiral rotation through coordination chemistry.Examples of Chirality Induction:
DAPI and DNA Interaction:.Opens in new tabThe chiroptical properties of DAPI when bound to DNA can be attributed to conformational changes induced by the interaction with the DNA. Magnetic Field Induction:.Opens in new tabUsing permanent magnets to rotate in space can generate chirality in materials by inducing a chiral structure. Flow-Induced Chirality:.Opens in new tabPressure-driven flow in a microfluidic cell can induce chiral structures in nematic liquid crystals. Self-Assembly of Tetraphenylethene (TPE):.Opens in new tabAchiral TPE molecules can self-assemble into chiral ribbons via solvophobic effects, which can be controlled by adjusting solvent composition and polarity. Chiral MOFs:.Opens in new tabPyridine can be used to induce chirality in MOFs assembled from achiral precursors.Applications:
Chiroptical Spectroscopy:Inducing chirality allows for the study of chiroptical properties, providing insights into molecular conformation and aggregation. Optical Devices and Metamaterials:Chiral structures can be used to create optical devices and metamaterials with applications in imaging, detection, and sensing. Anti-Counterfeiting:Chiral structures can be used as invisible signatures that are only visible through polarized lenses. Understanding Biological Chirality:Studying the induction of chirality in achiral systems can provide insights into the origin of biological chirality.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)